The Royal Australasian College of Physicians
Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying
November 2018
145 Macquarie Street, Sydney NSW 2000, Australia
Telephone +61 2 9256 5444 | Facsimile +61 2 9251 7476 | Email racpconsult@racp.edu.au
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
1
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
2
The RACP Statement
The RACP respects and supports all its members and does not believe it is appropriate or possible to
enforce a single view on a matter where individual conscience is important. The RACP recognises
that legalisation of voluntary assisted dying is for governments to decide, having regard to the will of
the community, to research, and to the views of medical and health practitioners.
Legislative change related to voluntary assisted dying will affect individual members in different ways.
Different clinical settings require ethical and clinical considerations to be made carefully, deliberately
and systematically. Our members are not unanimous in their support or opposition for legislative
change. The existence of divergent views constrains the RACP from developing a single position on
the legalisation of voluntary assisted dying.
The RACP takes the following unified positions if and where voluntary assisted dying is legalised:
Every patient should have access to timely, equitable, good quality end-of-life care, with
access to specialist palliative care where appropriate. These services must not be devalued.
On the specific issue of a competent adult in the last stages of incurable illness requesting
voluntary assistance to die, the RACP supports a clinical approach of critical neutrality to
encourage reflective dialogue.
Although physicians should not be forced to act outside their values and beliefs, they also
should not disengage from patients holding different values and beliefs, without ensuring that
arrangements for ongoing care are in place.
Patients seeking voluntary assisted dying should be made aware of the benefits of
palliative care. Referral to specialist palliative care should be strongly recommended but
cannot be made mandatory. Voluntary assisted dying must not be seen as part of
palliative care.
Legitimate concerns exist around protection of vulnerable individuals or groups.
Government, society and physicians must ensure that specific groups have equitable access
to palliative and end-of-life care, and that relationships of trust are not jeopardised. Specific
regard must be given to cultural and Indigenous experience.
All physicians must affirm the value of all patientslives, exploring reasons for requests for
voluntary assisted dying, while remaining alert to any signs of coercion and reduced capacity.
Assessments must not follow a ‘tick box’ approach. They must be underpinned by
adequate physician-patient relationships, including appropriate training, skill and experience.
Support, counselling and conflict mediation services must be available for individuals,
families and health professionals involved.
There must be rigorous documentation and data collection to enable review of any
scheme and to assess changes in practice and the impacts on health professionals, patients
and families.
This statement should not be taken as support for legislative change. The RACP will continue to
highlight concerns about legislative proposals, drawing on both clinical experience and the ethical
perspectives of our members. The RACP will continue to advocate for patient and physician well-
being in order to support our members and contribute our expertise as medical specialists who care
for dying patients.
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
3
Contents
Definitions................................................................................................................................................ 4
Introduction.............................................................................................................................................. 6
Part 1: The RACP Statement ................................................................................................................. 7
Part 2: Discussion of the Issues ............................................................................................................ 12
Part 3: Guidance and recommendations .............................................................................................. 23
References ............................................................................................................................................ 32
Acknowledgements
The RACP would like to acknowledge and thank those who led this work:
Dr George Laking, Chair Medical oncology
A/Prof Andrew Cole, Deputy Chair Rehabilitation medicine
Dr Jonathan Gillis Paediatric palliative medicine and intensive care
Dr James Howe - Neurology
Dr Danielle Ko Palliative medicine
Prof Paul Komesaroff Endocrinology and Medical Ethics
Dr Christopher McKinlay Neonatal/perinatal medicine
Dr Anthoulla Mohamudally Palliative medicine
Dr Linda Sheahan Palliative medicine
Dr Clare White Geriatric medicine
Supported by:
Ms Ritu Mohan - Senior Policy Officer, RACP
Ms Louise Hardy Manager, Policy & Advocacy, RACP
Mr Patrick Tobin Director, Policy & Advocacy, RACP
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
4
Definitions
Terms used in this document
Recognising that the overlap of terminologies is inexact and different formulations exist in the
literature, this statement uses the following terms and definitions:
Voluntary assisted dying includes:
1. prescription or supply of a lethal drug which a competent patient self-administers without
further assistance (sometimes called physician-assisted suicide’); or
2. administration of a lethal drug to a competent patient requesting assistance to die (sometimes
called voluntary euthanasia).
Children, those lacking competence and those not approaching the end of life are out of scope of this
definition and statement.
In each case the drug is made accessible at the request of a competent adult patient at the end of life
by a medical practitioner or other independent prescriber. The term is used descriptively and without a
priori judgement as to its ethical or legal standing.
The following are not considered to be voluntary assisted dying and are well established end-of-life
practices:
1. patient refusal of life-sustaining treatments: patients with capacity have the right to refuse
treatment including the provision of medically assisted nutrition and/or hydration
2. physician withholding or withdrawal of treatments that are not benefiting the patient:
physicians have a duty to consider the benefits and harms of any treatments, including the
provision of medically assisted nutrition and/or hydration, before instituting them. The benefits
and harms of ongoing treatment should also be regularly reviewed
3. provision of appropriate palliative sedation to manage refractory symptoms and
4. titration of medical treatment to relieve symptoms.
The RACP recognises that voluntary assisted dying, as defined above is distinct from and not part of
the practice of palliative care. It should be noted that the Australian and New Zealand Society of
Palliative Medicine (ANZSPM) has stated that ‘in accordance with best practice guidelines
internationally, the discipline of Palliative Medicine does not include the practices of [voluntary
assisted dying].’(1) This reflects statements from the International Association for Hospice and
Palliative Care, and the European Association for Palliative Care, that the provision of voluntary
assisted dying should not be included into the practice of palliative care.(2, 3) Likewise this position
of the ANZSPM position has been affirmed by the Australian and New Zealand Society of Geriatric
Medicine.(4)
End of life: patients are approaching the end of life when an experienced clinician would anticipate
death occurring within the next 6-12 months, even if the trajectory is uncertain. This includes those
living with:
1. advanced, progressive, incurable conditions, e.g. neurological or malignant disease
2. general frailty and co-existing conditions that mean that they are expected to die within 12
months and
3. life-threatening acute conditions caused by an irreversible sudden catastrophic event.
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
5
Dying: the terminal phase of life, where death is imminent and likely to occur within hours or days, or
occasionally weeks. This is sometimes referred to as ‘actively dying’.(5)
Palliative and supportive care: care provided by health professionals for people with a terminal or
serious physical illness that aims to:
1. optimise a patient’s quality of life until death by addressing their physical, psychosocial,
spiritual and cultural needs and
2. support the patient’s family, whānau, and other caregivers where needed, through the illness
and after death.(6)
Specialist palliative care: care provided by medical practitioners and other healthcare professionals
who are accredited by their training in palliative medicine and who work in the context of an expert
multidisciplinary team of palliative care professionals.
Double effect: the principle that there is a morally relevant difference between actions with
consequences that are both foreseen and intended, in contrast to actions with consequences that are
foreseen but not intended. Although philosophically disputed by some, the principle gives an
important legal and moral justification to provide treatment intended to relieve symptoms but that
could foreseeably but unintentionally hasten death.(7-11) Of particular note, the appropriate titration
of opioid medication for pain control does not hasten death,(12-16) and current evidence, although
limited, suggests that the use of sedation at the end of life does not have a significant impact on the
timing of death.(17)
Terms not used in this document
Debate on this topic has often become polarised. Much of the language has been loaded by
association with negative or disputed values. The following frequently used terms are therefore
avoided in this document:
1. euthanasia: disputed definition; sometimes associated with actions performed contrary to the
patient’s wishes
2. assisted suicide: negative connotations with the use of the word ‘suicide’; sometimes
associated with a more fundamentally independent action on the part of the patient, in which
providing support is overtly eschewed
3. death with dignity: disputed, as it can be used in a way that pre-supposes the validity of
arguments both for and against voluntary assisted dying
4. mercy killing: disputed as it is ambiguous as to the patient’s wishes
5. good death: disputed, as it can be used in a way that presupposes the validity of arguments
both for and against voluntary assisted dying.
Terms that are difficult to define
The following terms are important when discussing voluntary assisted dying but are complex and
difficult to define clearly or are used in a variety of ways which may be substantively relevant:
1. suffering: often conflated with physical pain, but considered to span categories including
physical, psychological, social, and spiritual or existential; Cicely Saunders’ total pain
concept is a parallel.(18) Suffering is also difficult to measure in an externally consistent way.
2. terminal illness: identifies incurability but is often used in a way that is unclear as to expected
length and quality of life; the terms end of lifeand dying” are considered to be more
generally useful here.
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
6
Introduction
In recent years, a number of proposals to legalise voluntary assisted dying have been considered by
Parliaments in Australia and New Zealand. As evidenced by recent public inquiries and sustained
reform attempts, there is significant community interest in having voluntary assisted dying as an
option at the end of life. Community sentiment has been informed by the impacts of illness on family
life, examples of distressing deaths, even suicide, and an appeal for greater control at the end of life.
The RACP acknowledges this is a complex and controversial topic and that while some physicians
will welcome contemporary discussion of the issues, other physicians may disapprove of the College
engaging in this space. The College’s work on this topic is grounded in the professional and civic
responsibility that all physicians have towards advancing the understanding of death and dying, and
promoting the best possible care for all people. This involves enhancing public discussion about all
aspects of end-of-life care and advocating for the delivery of good end-of-life care in physician
practice, hospitals, the health system and the community.
This statement is offered as guidance to physicians and policymakers, whilst acknowledging the
diversity of opinion of our membership and the complexities associated with end-of-life care.
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
7
Part 1: The RACP Statement
Part 1: The RACP Statement
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
8
1.1 Background
How did the RACP develop this Statement?
End-of-life care is an area in which current practice and service delivery too often falls short and has
been an area of focus for the RACP for a number of years. Following the launch of the RACP
position statement ‘Improving Care at the End of Life: Our Roles and Responsibilities (May 2016), the
RACP formed a working party in 2016 to develop a College statement on voluntary assisted dying
with the intention of offering a meaningful and contemporary contribution to policy debate. The
working party comprised physicians with a broad range of clinical and cultural expertise and
encompassed those with differing moral and ethical perspectives.
In developing this document, the working party followed an extensive consultation process, including
face-to-face and online consultation with Fellows, Trainees, College bodies, and Specialty Societies.
Conversations amongst Fellows and Trainees were focussed by external developments throughout
2017, including the introduction of bills and inquiries in the New Zealand, Victorian, New South Wales
and West Australian Parliaments, and the passage of the Victorian Voluntary Assisted Dying Bill in
November 2017 for commencement of the scheme in 2019.
The thoughts and perspectives shared by members have been extremely informative in developing
this statement. Face-to-face deliberations have involved deep thinking on the part of Fellows and
Trainees in working collaboratively through the complexities. Written submissions and online dialogue
have also enabled all interested members to express their view in a private and unstructured way. In
all cases, the views expressed have reminded working party members of the fact that physicians wear
many hats as patient advocates, medical leaders in the community, educators, colleagues,
members of religious and cultural communities, and as patients and family members themselves.
Why has the term ‘voluntary assisted dying’ been chosen?
The Working Party that developed this Statement was established in 2016 under the rubric of
“Euthanasia and Physician-Assisted Dying”. As noted above in the discussion of definitions, the
Working Party considered this language to be loaded, and to lead to polarised thinking and a
stalemate.
Accordingly, the Working Party proposed a change of the title to medical assistance in dying, as
used in Canada. The reception of the new language during the consultation phase was mixed. Some
Fellows and Trainees preferred to stay with assisted suicideand euthanasia’, viewing these as more
accurate descriptors. Other Fellows and Trainees supported medical assistance in dyingor preferred
the umbrella terms of assisted dyingand physician-assisted death’.
During the consultation, legislation to enable voluntary assisted dyingwas enacted in Victoria and
considered in New South Wales and Western Australia. In the end it seemed most practical to use the
prevalent legal language, accepting that all the terminology is to some extent disputed.
Voluntary assisted dying is currently illegal in New Zealand and in all Australian states and territories,
except Victoria where the Voluntary Assisted Dying Act 2017 is due to commence operation in June
2019. Medical organisations have historically been opposed to voluntary assisted dying (19, 20) and
while some physicians believe that this is the appropriate stance to take, others do not.
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
9
There is diverse opinion across the College about the professional involvement of physicians in
voluntary assisted dying. The College’s consultation process has highlighted this is a contentious
topic which goes to the heart of many physicians’ professional identity and beliefs.
During consultation, RACP members were asked for their view on a number of possible RACP
positions (we reproduce here the language used in consultation):
1. in opposition to any form of medical assistance in dying
2. of ‘studied neutrality’ to any form of medical assistance in dying, acknowledging that it is the
prerogative of society to decide whether laws should be changed and that there are diverse
views both within the College and society and
3. supporting medical assistance in dying; such support might be restricted to defined cases and
circumstances.
Separate from the above options, two possibilities were also set out as to how the RACP might
engage on the issue:
1. decline to take part in further public discussions around proposed legislation or
2. continue to take part in discussions around proposed legislation in order to exert its influence
on issues such as safeguards, conscientious objection and protection for our members.
Throughout consultation, Fellows and Trainees expressed views ranging from strong opposition to
strong support, with concerns about the implications for vulnerable people, impact upon families and
practitioners where different individuals express different preferences for care, and professionals’
(dis)comfort in these settings.
This range of views led the Working Party to recommend the College focus its Statement away from
political advocacy and towards practical guidance for physicians dealing with this challenging topic.
Critical neutralitywas proposed as a clinical approach to encourage respectful and reflective
dialogue with patients, families and colleagues who might have differing views. Critical neutrality is a
term with its origins in educational practice.(21) It is an approach that avoids imposing ones own
values on another person in favour of helping them find their way to a conclusion consistent with their
own set of values.
1.2 Common ground
The RACP has striven to foster collegiality and respect throughout dialogue with members. Common
ground arises regarding the following values that unite all physicians when considering care at the
end of life:
1. Patients and families are at the centre of clinical practice.
2. Death and dying are a natural and inevitable part of life.
3. It is the shared aim of all physicians to provide good medical care throughout the lifespan,
including at the end of life.
4. High quality end-of-life care, including specialist palliative care, and high quality aged care should
be readily accessible to all.
5. There are many ways to consider human dignity.
6. Most people near the end of life value their life in many ways and their life is valued by those who
love, care for and treat them, including their medical teams.
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
10
7. People should be entitled to make autonomous decisions about their care, recognising that end-
of-life decisions are best made with involvement of individuals, families/carers and health
professionals.
8. Some individuals may find value in their suffering through their own cultural, spiritual and religious
beliefs while other individuals may find no value in suffering.
9. Palliative and supportive care can alleviate much pain, related symptoms and loss of function, but
cannot relieve all suffering for all people in all circumstances.
10. Where voluntary assisted dying is legalised in Australia or New Zealand, it would be a steep
change in how end-of-life care is practised and perceived.
11. Both proponents and opponents of voluntary assisted dying say they are motivated to ease
suffering and provide high-quality care at the end of life.
1.3 The RACP Statement
The RACP respects and supports all its members and does not believe it is appropriate or possible to
enforce a single view on a matter where individual conscience is important. The RACP recognises
that legalisation of voluntary assisted dying is for governments to decide, having regard to the will of
the community, to research, and to the views of medical and health practitioners.
Legislative change related to voluntary assisted dying will affect individual members in different ways.
Different clinical settings require ethical and clinical considerations to be made carefully, deliberately
and systematically. Our members are not unanimous in their support or opposition for legislative
change. The existence of divergent views constrains the RACP from developing a single position on
the legalisation of voluntary assisted dying.
The RACP takes the following unified positions if and where voluntary assisted dying is legalised:
Every patient should have access to timely, equitable, good quality end-of-life care, with
access to specialist palliative care where appropriate. These services must not be devalued.
On the specific issue of a competent adult in the last stages of incurable illness requesting
voluntary assistance to die, the RACP supports a clinical approach of critical neutrality to
encourage reflective dialogue.
Although physicians should not be forced to act outside their values and beliefs, they also
should not disengage from patients holding different values and beliefs without ensuring that
arrangements for ongoing care are in place.
Patients seeking voluntary assisted dying should be made aware of the benefits of
palliative care. Referral to specialist palliative care should be strongly recommended but
cannot be made mandatory. Voluntary assisted dying must not be seen as part of palliative
care.
Legitimate concerns exist around protection of vulnerable individuals or groups.
Government, society and physicians must ensure that specific groups have equitable access
to palliative and end-of-life care and that relationships of trust are not jeopardised. Specific
regard must be given to cultural and Indigenous experience.
All physicians must affirm the value of all patientslives, exploring reasons for requests for
voluntary assisted dying while remaining alert to any signs of coercion and reduced capacity.
Assessments must not follow a ‘tick box’ approach. They must be underpinned by
adequate physician-patient relationships, including appropriate training, skill and experience.
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
11
Support, counselling and conflict mediation services must be available for individuals,
families and health professionals involved.
There must be rigorous documentation and data collection to enable review of any
scheme and to assess changes in practice and the impacts on health professionals, patients
and families.
This statement should not be taken as support for legislative change. The RACP will continue to
highlight concerns about legislative proposals, drawing on both clinical experience and the ethical
perspectives of our members. The RACP will continue to advocate for patient and physician well-
being in order to support our members and contribute our expertise as medical specialists who care
for dying patients.
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
12
Part 2: Discussion of the Issues
Part 2: Discussion of the Issues
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
13
2.1 Historic framing of the issues
Researchers and commentators in the academic, legal and medical literature have explored and
debated voluntary assisted dying, under its various guises, for many years.(22-29) Although a
complete history of this work is beyond this paper’s scope, a brief review is pertinent.
Historical claims in favour of legalisation (these have been contested):
1. Individual autonomy. Individuals have the right to make their own decisions about health
care, are best placed to make quality-of-life assessments for themselves, and want control
and choice at the end of life.(30-32)
2. Avoidance of suffering. Physical, psychological, social, spiritual and existential suffering that
occurs in dying can be avoided or minimised where voluntary assisted dying is available.(33-
35)
3. Harm minimisation. International studies have shown that these practices are happening
even when illegal.(36-40) Legalisation will serve to regulate this activity, in turn allowing for it
to be monitored and for appropriate safeguards against abuse to be set up.
4. The ethical continuum of end-of-life decision-making. Voluntary assisted dying lies on a
continuum of end-of-life decision-making where hastened death is the intention; because no
categorical distinction is seen to exist in such a continuum, it is ethically justified in the same
way.(41-44)
Claims in opposition to legalisation (these have also been contested):
1. The value of life and community interest in not taking life are paramount. In the past,
communities were prepared to sacrifice life only where it was justified on a community level,
for example in conflict or penal settings. (45)
2. The meaning of autonomy may be more elusive than it at first appears in light of issues
such as the change in preferences over time (e.g. regret), concern about decision making
capacity in different settings, and the intersection of biopsychosocial, spiritual, and cultural
dimensions with free will.
3. Risk of damage to the doctor’s role as healer and erosion of trust in the doctor patient
relationship.(46) Formulations include:
a) “doctors are not authorised morally to take life”;
b) incredulity that doctors would be asked to take on this role, suggesting that it could be
handed to some other technical profession with appropriate legal support;
c) traditional medical paradigms hold the supposed primacy of doing no harm to patients
and the preservation of life as paramount and deliberate action to cause death runs
counter to the purpose of medicine; and
d) legalising and endorsing doctorscapacity to take life may erode trust in the doctor
patient relationship, in that the patient relies on the doctors assumed obligation to do
no harm; this is particularly acute for groups in society who already distrust
doctors.(47)
4. Risk to vulnerable groups and individuals, and so-called slippery slope
arguments.(48-50) This slippery slope argument has many forms, but essentially it states
that if voluntary assisted dying is legalised, the potential exists for:
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
14
a) pressure on vulnerable persons to seek voluntary assisted dying when it is actually in
someone else’s interest that they do so;
b) widening of the clinical criteria to include other groups in society, for example those
who are tired of life; voluntary assisted dying then supplants other remedies that
people have for their non-end-of-life problems;
c) an increase in instances of non-voluntary and involuntary medicalised ending of life;
d) progressive devaluation of life culturally; and
e) financial toxicity, for example through people being quantified in terms of their assets
(e.g. housing value) and this being weighed up against expenditure on care.
5. Moral loss that comes with avoidance of suffering or by controlling time and method of
death. Some moral traditions including those described as Stoic have perceived value in
some types of suffering and do not necessarily see patient or doctor control of death as a
good.(51)
2.2 Data from other jurisdictions
Jurisdictions with established legal mechanisms to support voluntary assisted dying (under various
names) include the Netherlands, Belgium, Luxembourg, Switzerland, and the American states of
Oregon, Washington State, Vermont and Montana. More recently, legalisation has occurred in
Canada and in the American states of California, Colorado and Washington D.C.
In this section, data coming out of US regions and Europe are presented. This may inform thinking in
the Australasian context. Generalisations and extrapolations around such a complex issue cannot be
easily made (52) and readers should note that there may be other sources of information available
which shed new light on the information below. Emerging data from recently legalised jurisdictions,
whilst not covered here, may also be valuable in understanding new implementation experiences for
example, anecdotal reports from Canada of doctors who have provided medical assistance in dying
once and who do not wish to be involved again.(53)
Oregon and Washington State
In Oregon and Washington State, eligible adults may be prescribed the lethal medication by a doctor.
Patients who choose to take the medication must take it without assistance. The term used is
physician-assisted suicide.
Rates are increasing although remain low proportionally to all deaths.(54-56) In Oregon in 2017, the
rate of reported deaths was 39.9 per 10,000 deaths.(57, 58) In 2016, (58) reported physician-assisted
suicide accounted for 0.37% of all deaths in Oregon. The majority of patients were 65 years of age or
older (80.4%), with median age 74 years. Decedents were almost all white (94.4%), often well
educated (48.9% university level), and had cancer as a primary illness (76.9%), followed by
amyotrophic lateral sclerosis (7.0%) and heart/circulatory disease (6.3%).(57, 58)
Of the minority of people who access this option, not all patients take the prescribed lethal medication.
However, the majority do, and for some the data are missing - in 2017, 218 prescriptions were written,
and 144 (66.05%) are known to have died from ingesting the prescribed medication. Ingestion status
for 44 patients is unknown for 2017.(57, 58) Most patients died at home (90.2%).(57, 58)
The most frequently cited end-of-life concerns were loss of autonomy (87.4%), decreasing ability to
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
15
participate in activities that made life enjoyable (88.1%) and loss of dignity, though dignity is
undefined (67.1%).(57-59) Studies have investigated the patient drivers and uncontrolled physical
symptoms, including pain, are not the primary issue. (60, 61) Of note, only a small proportion of
patients accessed the law based on fear of uncontrolled symptoms such as pain.
Reported complication rates are low but data in 50% of cases are missing. Between 1998-2017 in
Oregon, 1275 patients took the lethal medications; data are missing in 638 cases. Seven patients
regained consciousness after ingesting the medication, and 25 reported difficulty ingesting or reported
regurgitating.
(57, 58)
In 2017 a total of 92 physicians wrote 218 prescriptions (1-29 prescriptions per physician). There has
been some evidence collated from the state-wide statistics that a small number of participating
physicians are responsible for a significant concentration of the fatal prescriptions in Oregon, with
61% of the fatal barbiturate prescriptions in 2001 to 2007 written by 18%of the participating
physicians, and 23% written by only 3 of the 109 participating physicians.(62, 63) No referrals to the
medical board were made for failure to comply.(57, 58)
Undiagnosed depression may be an issue. In Oregon 5% of patients received psychiatric evaluation.
In Washington State 4% were referred for psychiatric evaluation.(64, 65) A retrospective review found
that some patients prescribed lethal medications had signs and symptoms of depression and
remained undiagnosed.(66)
Europe (Benelux Countries and Switzerland)
Eligible persons may be prescribed the lethal medication by a doctor. The prevalent term is assisted
suicide. Patients who choose to take the medication may self-administer it or, more commonly,
request that a doctor administer it. In Switzerland, only self-administration is legal.
The incidence of assisted suicide is rising. Data (including unreported cases) show it accounted for
about 4.6% of all deaths in Belgium in 2013 (67) and 4% of all deaths in the Netherlands in 2016.(68,
69) Of all deaths by assisted suicide in the Netherlands in 2016, 48.6% of persons were female,
36.9% occurred in persons under 70 years old and 33 occurred in persons over 80 years old.(68, 69)
While this indicates a younger group than in the US states, data indicate increasing access among
those 80 or older.(70)
In Belgium and the Netherlands, almost all assisted suicide occurs at home and by injection of lethal
medication rather than by a self-administered oral medication.
There is evidence from the Netherlands that notwithstanding strict legal guidelines, the scheme may
have been open to abuse.(71-74) In the Netherlands and Belgium, patient concerns/reasons are not
officially recorded in a consistent way. However there is evidence in Belgium that reasons such as
tired of lifeare increasing.(75, 76) There have been some qualitative studies of families and patients
(77, 78), but most data come from physicians retrospectively reporting the motivations of their
patients.
In the Netherlands, complications such as inability to insert an intravenous cannula, vomiting up of
oral medications, and the patient either not dying or taking a very long time to die are reported to have
occurred.(29, 79)
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
16
In February 2014, Belgium extended its euthanasia laws to also apply to children of any age with a
terminal illness.(80) Attention has turned toward the extensions of the legislation to consider enabling
other groups who may want access to assisted suicide(e.g. people with refractory mental illness,
minors and patients with cognitive impairment.(81-84)
While the evaluation of palliative care servicing is contested, underdevelopment of services has not
as yet been linked empirically to uptake of assisted suicide.(85)
Vulnerable groups
Vulnerable groups measured in the data groupings do not appear to be overrepresented based on the
reported numbers accessing voluntary assisted dying in both regions. The available data do not show
evidence of increased relative risk to vulnerable groups, and no sustained increase in the incidence of
life-ending medical interventions without the explicit request or consent of the individual patient.(86)
The exception to this is the HIV positive population.
The caveat is that not all vulnerable groups are necessarily identified. Vulnerable groups reported in
the overseas studies include low socioeconomic status, females, the elderly and nursing home
patients.(86, 87)
2.3 Socio-cultural context
Advances in medical treatment and public health have meant that many people are living longer and
healthier lives, with the burden of illness shifting to the last stages of life. This has led to a shift from
acute treatable conditions to chronic degenerative diseases and cancers as the main cause of death
in adults.
This in turn has changed the way in which many of us die, with many deaths occurring in hospital or
intensive care settings. These deaths more frequently involve human intervention,(88) creating a
sense that dying can be negotiated. Death and dying may therefore be seen as something to fear or
as a failureof care at the end of life both by healthcare professionals and by some parts of society.
Many surveys on attitudes towards voluntary assisted dying in the peer-reviewed academic literature
in English-speaking countries have identified public and professional support.(36, 89-96) Peer-review
notwithstanding, survey results have been criticised based on how the issue is framed and questions
formulated.(29, 97) Survey results also often lack detail on the definition of exactly what form of
assisted dying is being discussed, the way responses are interpreted, the population surveyed, and
the quantification of the results. Similarly, opinion polls undertaken by media and researchers in
Australia and New Zealand find majority public support for voluntary assisted dying for competent
adults who are terminally ill and suffering.(98-102) It is likely that such surveys and polls have
contributed to a political perception of wide public support for legalisation to enable voluntary assisted
dying and it is conceivable that public views would be more ambivalent if more sophisticated cases
and scenarios were considered.
Various ideas have been examined in the literature as to the socio-cultural reasons for community
interest in voluntary assisted dying. These include increased reliance on science and technologies,
the routinisation of life-extending practices, and the medicalisation of dying.(103) It has also been
argued that Western societal value placed on individualism and efficiency affects attitudes towards
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
17
death and the conditions that dying people and their carers face.
(104) This may provide some link to
realities in the United States where the common demographic profile of persons who have received
voluntary assisted dying (see above) is white and well-educated.(29)
In multicultural countries such as Australia and New Zealand, it should be recognised that many
cultures believe an individual is a person in relationship to others, reflecting a culture-specific
approach to autonomy and a preference towards more communal end-of-life decision making and
planning.
Indigenous perspectives
There are a range of Indigenous community views and what follows is just a limited sample.
The RACP Aboriginal and Torres Strait Islander Health Committee has highlighted the nuance needed
around Indigenous understandings of death and dying. Whilst much remains to be described about the
Indigenous Australian setting, these understandings include connection to country and dying on
country, particularly outside metropolitan areas, as well as different concepts of family and quality of
life. There is an unmet need for access to culturally appropriate end-of-life care amongst this group,
with geographical and other access issues compounding the gap. This would appear to be the utmost
priority in improving end-of-life care for Indigenous Australians.
Across the Tasman, the New Zealand Parliament has been considering the End of Life Choice Bill
which proposes to give those with a terminal illness or a grievous and irremediable medical condition
the option of requesting voluntary assisted dying. The RACP was provided the following Māori
perspective on the Bill which describes some of the discomfort that may arise in this area:
The End of Life Choice Bill does not acknowledge the existence of a mātauranga Māori [Māori
worldview] approach to death and dying, which can vary within whānau, hapū, and iwi
[extended family, subtribe, and tribe]. Some of the assumptions underpinning the Bill, including
ideas of ‘choiceand dignityas used in the Bill, are not in fact universal but are based on
cultural assumptions.
Dying and sickness from a mātauranga Māori perspective do not happen solely to the
individual. This is reflected for example in the practice of kirimate and whānau pani (bereaved
whānau). In these practices (which vary from rohe to rohe [area to area]) the close family of the
deceased effectively enter into the world of the dead during the tangihanga [wake and funeral]
and become highly tapu [sacred], and are returned to the world of the living through their
participation in the hakari [feasting] and other rituals.(105)
The body is important in the traditional Māori funeral custom. The wairua (spirit) of the deceased
is considered to stay by its body at first and needs encouragement to start on the journey to the
next world. This underscores the importance of the body as a focus for Māori funeral custom
(tangihanga). When a Māori patient dies it is critical that the whānau has prompt access to the
tūpapaku [corpse]. If a post-mortem is required this must be done as soon as feasible.(106)
The New Zealand Committee of the RACP upholds a Māori perspective on death and dying:
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
18
“An important cultural consideration in Te Ao Māori is that the mauri [life force] of a person is
independent from their brain; in this context spiritual presence is still respected during physical
and psychological deterioration. Furthermore, the mana of an iwi and whānau is often relative
to the number of kaumātua (elders) present. As such, independent of whether Māori elderly are
in poor health their continuing presence is seen as enhancing the mana of their Marae and
people”.
The assumption that death is purely about individual choice is a faulty one. This also makes problematic
the processes as outlined in the End of Life Choice Bill, especially the lack of whānau involvement in
key decision making points.
The Bill also fails to acknowledge the problematic relationship between Māori and social policy and
legislation. While it makes claims as to the efficacy of the legislative safeguards for the vulnerable in
other jurisdictions, it does not allow for the historical and social context that is unique to New Zealand.
In this context, seemingly universal legislation often has a disproportionately negative impact on Māori.
This is noticeable in many spheres of New Zealand life including education, justice and health. Factors
such as unconscious biascan influence how policy is implemented in such areas, are not accounted
for in legislation and end with outcome disparities in many areas for Māori.
2.4 Issues raised from clinical experience
Individual patient situations at the end of life involve multiple factors which are often complex. Based
on professional experience, many patients do not fit neatly into particular rules or situations. The
codification of medical practice by law can create reassurance in some situations but can also work
against the careful deliberative negotiation of complexity favoured in physician practice. In this way,
even a well-drafted law can be defeated by clinical complexities. Factors that increase complexity
include:
1. defining what is a terminal illness;
2. estimating life expectancy and the imminence of dying;
3. exploring the reasons for a request;
4. judging whether an individual’s mental state is affecting their ability to decide;
5. assessing a person’s capacity to make a request for voluntary assisted dying, especially in
those who are debilitated, have reduced mental capacity or have other diseases and
problems that affect decision-making; and
6. defining enduring and unbearable sufferingthat cannot be relieved in a manner the patient
deems tolerable.
Here we provide examples of the complexity inherent in everyday clinical situations. The following are
by no means the only issues that could arise in this area.
Defining end of life and estimating life expectancy
Many illnesses will eventually cause the person’s death. Even so, the time frames can be uncertain.
Cancer is the main disease which many people think of in the context of requests for voluntary
assisted dying. In many situations cancer is a predictable cause of death but different types of cancer
have different trajectories. Some cancers (for example adenocarcinoma of pancreas or small cell
carcinoma of lung) often have an aggressive course and poor survival, whereas others (such as
adenocarcinoma of prostate) may have an indolent course where the person may be expected to die
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
19
with the cancer but of other causes. Even with specific cancers there is variation in how they behave,
with some lung cancers (e.g. EGFR-mutated adenocarcinomas of lung treated with tyrosine kinase
inhibitors) in some patients taking many years to cause death. Uncertainty is an inescapable part of
medicine, especially when it comes to estimating prognosis.
Other diseases such as heart failure or severe respiratory disease such as chronic obstructive
pulmonary disease will also prove fatal for many people. However, trajectories for these illnesses are
typically characterised by exacerbations followed by periods of stability. Even when these illnesses
are severe and at their end stage, it is difficult to predict life expectancy in an individual person. All
physicians will recall experiences of treating patients with severe organ failure who they believed were
going to die very soon but then improved to survive beyond expectation.
The situation is even more difficult where one or other form of dementia or slow neurodegenerative
condition (e.g. Parkinson’s disease) is present, where disease trajectory may be highly variable and
the occurrence of other illnesses, such as infections, as a cause of acute deterioration leading to end
of life is quite unpredictable.
Being confident of a 12-month lifespan on an individual basis is therefore very difficult. As expressed
in a recent systematic review,(107) accurate forecasting is (nearly) impossible for a number of
reasons explained below.
Prognostication is not only affected by patient factors but also by the level of clinician experience,
duration of relationship with the patient and whether it is done by an individual or a multidisciplinary
team. It is based on statistical data which will only apply on average. Therefore, if a certain group of
patients have a median 12-month expectation of life, half will die before this time and half afterwards.
Studies are also heterogeneous. Most studies have been in the cancer population and there are
studies in non-cancer populations that show forecasting is even more inaccurate in those settings.
As described in the review, there are also varying types of estimates (continuous, categorical and
probabilistic) and of the three estimates, probabilistic estimates “may be slightly more accurate than
categorical or continuous”.(107)
Studies show that clinicians are more likely to overestimate than underestimate survival.
Exploring the reasons for a request
Careful examination of the psychodynamic issues that may be involved in making and receiving
requests for assisted dying is critical. Questions should be asked about what is going on in the
patient’s mind, the practitioner’s mind, and the interactions between the two (not to mention family
members, other health care professionals and societal and institutional mores).
People approaching death may experience intense periods of existential reflection and physical
challenge. The motivations behind expressing a desire to die or requesting hastened death may be
complex.(108) For example, such requests may be a vehicle to express other concerns, such as a
fear of being a burden on others, fear of loss of control or fear of loss of a sense of self and
dignity.(109) Other motivations may be more immediate, such as poor symptom control and suffering.
It is however important to note that only a small proportion of patients in Oregon access assisted
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
20
suicide based on fear of uncontrolled symptoms such as pain: rather, loss of autonomy is most
frequently cited.(57)
Peoples wishes and preferences for death in certain conditions may change during their illnesses.
For example, there is a study from Belgium of patients with locked-in syndrome who at first sought
assisted suicide but changed their perspective over time.(110)
Reduced food and fluid intake, with poor appetite, switching to catabolic metabolism and significant
weight loss, is very common as the end of a person’s life approaches. In this setting, many family
members feel very conflicted if food brought to a patient as a symbol of love and care is refused.
More generally, misguided and poorly-informed public comment may centre around dying people
:”starving to death, where images of starvation in younger people are incorrectly transposed onto
perceptions of end-of-life care in these patients and used to justify voluntary assisted dying.
This is regarded by many specialists as a normal part of the body’s shut-down process at the end of
life and can be well-managed, like other end-of-life symptoms, with palliative care. Exploring each of
the issues of concern is critical in providing good end-of-life care.
People with concerns about end-of-life care may request voluntary assisted dying for themselves or a
family member even though symptom relief and a peaceful death may be available by other palliative
means. Individuals may need to be reassured of the following:
1. Palliative care is not exclusively for people in the last weeks to days of life. Supportive
and palliative care can be delivered alongside disease modifying treatment at any time.
Palliative care aims to improve the quality of life of patients and their families facing life-
threatening illness through the prevention and relief of suffering.
2. Intolerable suffering at the end of life is not inevitable. The vast majority of symptoms that
may cause suffering in the terminal phase can be anticipated and treated.
3. Withholding or withdrawing life sustaining treatment in a dying person allows natural
death from the underlying disease processes. This is already a normal part of end-of-life
care and can be explored through advance care planning discussions.
4. Administering treatment for the express purpose of ending life is not the same as
palliative sedation and the use of opioids for pain relief and symptoms resistant to other
treatments.
(111-114)
5. The appropriate titration of opioid medication for pain control does not hasten death(96-
100) and current evidence, although limited, suggests that use of sedation at the end of
life does not have a significant impact on the timing of death.(17)
Although studies have shown that people have many non-medical concerns at the end of life, it is
freedom from pain that is generally the most wished for outcome by patients, families and health
professionals.(115) Although significant numbers of :”clandestineend-of-life practices have been
reported in the literature, there are no reports of such practices in the context of palliative care in
Australasia.(36, 116)
Access to social and community support and financial concerns are factors that may also play a role
in motivating requests. These include social isolation and the cost/availability of suitable nursing home
placements, long-term care for young patients and respite for carers.
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
21
Assessment of mental state in the context of end-of-life care
People approaching the end of life often report emotions such as anger, grief, hopelessness, guilt,
regret and existential emptiness. These may manifest in ways that resemble depressive symptoms,
such as poor appetite, hopelessness, nihilistic thinking, low self-esteem and anhedonia. Clinicians
often face a challenge in differentiating such symptoms, which may lead to a request for voluntary
assisted dying, from treatable clinical depressive illness, which left alone or treated inappropriately,
may itself lead to suicide.
Other mental and cognitive disorders may need to be taken into consideration, particularly in the
elderly, and like the symptoms mentioned above, may vary at different points in a person’s illness. All
these things can complicate the medico-legal assessment of competence.
Attributes of decision-making capacity include the ability to understand the facts involved, understand
the main choices, weigh up the consequences of the choices, understand how the consequences,
affect them, and communicate their decision.(117) Such capacity can exist even where the option
selected is not what other people might choose. Consistency with previously held beliefs and values
may also be taken into account.(117) Capacity is assessed for a specific decision and is not a global
requirement. A person might not have the capacity to make complex decisions but nonetheless be
able to make more basic ones. People who are unwell may temporarily lose capacity to make
decisions but regain it when they become well again.
Assessment of capacity is commonly undertaken in clinical practice. Examples include decisions
about whether to have a surgical procedure or medical treatment, the ability to manage one’s own
finances, appoint a power of attorney, and whether to live at home or move into residential aged care.
Under normal circumstances capacity is assumed to be present unless sufficient reason exists to
question it. Physicians in Australia and New Zealand are familiar with assessing capacity in relation to
decisions around specific procedures or treatments or in ordering personal affairs, but are much less
familiar with how to do this in the complex context of a request for voluntary assisted dying. Several
cases from the common law have highlighted the need for greater certainty about criminal liability and
about how competence should be tested in such cases.(118)
Defining enduring and unbearable sufferingthat cannot be relieved in a
manner the patient deems tolerable
Many people assume that requests for voluntary assisted dying are made predominantly because of
unrelieved pain. Suffering is a far broader concept than physical pain.(119) It is not for health
professionals to judge whether symptoms are unbearable for the patient. The main drivers of requests
for voluntary assisted dying are not unrelieved physical pain.(29) Significant topics in relation to the
nature of suffering at the end of life include existential distress and feelings of lack of physical and
temporal control.
Potential impact on already complex care
The care of the dying is a complex intersection of immediate and anticipated needs. As well as
symptom management, physicians must think ahead on such things as the options for withdrawal of
treatment, and what to do when decision making capacity is lost. They must negotiate these topics
with reference to the person’s wishes as expressed to them directly and mediated via their families.
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
22
They must communicate their own knowledge and experience in a way that supports the learnings of
both patient and family. Community health literacy around death and dying is generally estimated to
be poor, at least in the time before people find themselves in these situations.(120)
Legislation to enable voluntary assisted dying could further complicate this aspect of physician care.
Some patients and families may experience concern that decisions may be made without a person’s
consent, regardless of the wording of the law. Physician involvement in voluntary assisted dying, were
it to become legally available, is likely to have consequences for all people, not only the ones who
want to access this choice, but for all families - both of those who seek this choice, and in other
circumstances, those who do not seek this choice, not to mention those families where there is no
unity about a given choice by an individual patient. There could also be unintended effects on the
end-of-life care of patients excluded from legislation.
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
23
Part 3: Guidance and recommendations
Part 3: Guidance and Recommendations
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
24
3.1 Guidance for physicians
The depth of feedback from Fellows and Trainees highlights that the issues are complex and should
not be viewed in binary terms. Voluntary assisted dying is not a single concept but is used to refer to a
variety of different practices with differing implications. The relevant values and how to prioritise them
for each case may be different for individual physicians. The RACP encourages physicians to
consider their own stance on the issues.
Regardless of physicians’ personal views or intentions in this regard, physician practice is likely to be
affected in Victoria and other jurisdictions where medical assistance might in future be legalised.
Some guiding principles are therefore needed. Common ground is shared by all physicians by
focusing on patients and their clinical care. This includes principles that can be inferred from the usual
attributes of physician practice.
1. End-of-life care
a. All physicians have a duty to provide high quality end-of-life care to patients, families and
carers. This involves:
open and honest communication with patients and their families and carers about
impending death;
a doctor-patient relationship based on openness, trust and good communication;
recognising the positive contribution a physician can make to end-of-life care; and
acknowledging and respecting different cultural preferences and approaches to death
and dying and providing culturally sensitive end-of-life care.
2. Care that is centred on the patient and the family
a. Patient and family expectations may differ from a physician’s values and conception of good
medical care.
b. The challenge will be for physicians to approach this issue from patients’ and families’ frames
of reference.
c. The ultimate aim is to help patients and families find their way to decisions that reflect their
own goals and values in the context of end-of-life care.
3. Professionalism
a. Physicians are encouraged to consider their own values and beliefs on voluntary assisted
dying, how they may handle a patient request and, if legalised, to what degree they may feel
able to participate. This may be informed by a range of considerations such as their moral
and ethical perspectives, patient need, individual beliefs and clinical experiences.
b. It is important that physicians respect colleagues who may have differing opinions.
c. No physician should feel that they have to act outside their values and beliefs and the RACP
will continue to advocate in this regard.
d. Physicians should have regard for the wellbeing of both themselves and their colleagues.
e. See also the Domains of expertiseon Page 28.
4. Communication skills:
a. Requests for voluntary assisted dying are also requests for communication.
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
25
b. Communication skills are essential to fully explore patient requests for voluntary assisted
dying and any underlying reasons for these requests that can be managed in other ways.
c. A person’s will to live may fluctuate in the last phase of their life, even as death seems
imminent. By communication the physician can identify sources of anxiety, fear and suffering
and effective ways of treating or managing these.
d. The professional empowerment of physicians will depend on continuing to develop and refine
their skills and knowledge to engage in end-of-life conversations, especially where these may
move into areas of conflict with physicians’ own values and beliefs.
3.2 Recommendations for policymakers
The RACP has concerns about the potential for legalised voluntary assisted dying to jeopardise
vulnerable populations, be abused, expose health practitioners to professional risk, harm patients and
families and erode trust in the medical profession. If parliaments in Australia or New Zealand decide
that laws should be changed, the development of laws, regulations and guidelines must be
undertaken in consultation with medical and health experts, the RACP and other medical and health
organisations.
Some key recommendations for policymakers are set out below. These have been developed in
consultation with our members as the RACP responded to legislative proposals during 2017. The
issues are connected with the accessibility of good end-of-life care.
The recommendations stated in the RACP’s position statement
‘Improving Care at the End of Life:
Our Roles and Responsibilities (May 2016) should also be referred to in this context, including:
supporting system changes including enabling health professionals to take the time they need
to discuss end-of-life care with patients, and to conduct and document family/whānau
conferences including goals-of-care discussions, appropriate social work support and
bereavement care;
providing adequate resources in the community to support patients wishing to die at home, in
a hospice or in a residential aged care facility;
ensuring patients can access specialist palliative care support as needed, at any time of day
or night;
streamlining patient information to ensure health professionals have access to key patient
information and documents; and
funding systems to measure and benchmark outcomes of end-of-life care.
Inequitable access to good quality end-of-life care persists for many Australian citizens. This includes
Aboriginal and Torres Strait Islander people and people from culturally and linguistically diverse
backgrounds. Other groups that experience inequitable access to care include people with intellectual
disability acquired or congenital, patients dying from diseases other than cancers, and people living
in residential aged care facilities, some of whom are under 65 years of age, living with one or more
chronic diseases. Inconsistent care is more prevalent in rural and remote communities in
Australia.(121) Similar issues apply in New Zealand, especially for Māori.(122-124)
Governments must remain vigilant in the areas of palliative care and aged care and commit adequate
resourcing to ensure that good end-of-life care is being delivered to all citizens. Every patient should
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
26
receive timely, equitable, good quality end-of-life care, including access to specialist palliative care
where appropriate.
If and where voluntary assisted dying is legalised
1. End-of-life care and palliative care
Recommendations regarding end-of-life care and palliative care:
The need for palliative care services must not be devalued; indeed, palliative care must be
given even greater priority and resourcing than it is now.
Governments must ensure that all patients have access to good end-of-life care and
palliative care as needed. This includes equitable access for populations that currently
experience poor access, such as people from rural, regional and remote areas, Culturally
and Linguistically Diverse backgrounds, Indigenous backgrounds, people with intellectual
disability, patients dying from diseases other than cancers, and people living in residential
aged care facilities.
Governments and oversight bodies must dedicate resources to closely examine voluntary
assisted dying requests that arise where the patient actually has poor options for good end-
of-life care, for example in circumstances where symptom relief and a peaceful death
cannot be provided to the patient because of limited access to palliative and supportive
care.
Patients seeking voluntary assisted dying must be made aware of the benefits that
palliative care can offer at the end of life and referral to specialist palliative care should be
strongly recommended.
However, palliative care referral or consultation after a request for voluntary assisted dying
has been made cannot be mandatory given:
o consultation or referral to palliative care services, like any medical referral, is not
mandated and is a care option that a patient may or may not choose to accept;
o legalisation of voluntary assisted dying in any form will create significant challenges
for palliative medicine specialists and palliative care organisations;
o voluntary assisted dying must not be seen as part of palliative care - these are
distinct practices; and
o the risk that involvement of palliative care referral and/or consultation is simply
seen as, and becomes, a procedural step or tick-the-boxexercise.
Consideration of a more formal legal clarification of the principle of double effect is an
important, but separate, issue from the legalisation of voluntary assisted dying.
The Victorian scheme due to commence in June 2019 requires a number of complex end
of life conversations with individuals and assessments to be undertaken. Physicians must
be able to take the time required for these consultations.
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
27
2. Conscientious objection
In general, where objections of conscience have arisen in medical practice in Australia and New
Zealand, clinicians have accepted they should refer patients to another practitioner. However, for
some physicians the moral impact of referring a request for voluntary assisted dying to a willing
practitioner may be felt deeply. The RACP holds that physicians should not be forced to refer, but
neither should they hinder patients from accessing such services.
Conscientious objection affects not only the medical practitioner but the multidisciplinary team treating
the patient. Conscientious objection may also occur for other non-medical individuals within
multidisciplinary teams or at an institutional level.
Conscientious objection may present issues in certain settings, for example amongst inpatients of an
objecting hospital or hospice, those who are unable to go to another clinic, practitioners who would
perform voluntary assisted dying but are not accredited at a given site, and patients living in rural
areas serviced only by an objecting practitioner(s).
Protections should be available for participating or objecting practitioners who do not wish to be
identified. Some practitioners might encounter stigma, victimisation, harassment and other issues
relating to the perception by patients, families, colleagues and the broader community, if a public
register of practitioners were to be mandated. A practitioner may not want to be identified because
they are concerned that patients will not come to see them if they are known to be participating in
voluntary assisted dying. Conversely, a patient may refuse to see a doctor if they choose not to
participate. This could compromise timely assessment and care in a geographical area where there
are limited doctors to see.
It should also be recognised that some practitioners may be willing to participate in voluntary assisted
dying for eligible patients in restricted ways, e.g. in a limited range of cases, or in only providing a
second opinion.
Recommendations regarding conscientious objection:
Physicians should not be forced to refer, but neither should they hinder patients from
accessing such services.
A central information source on the scheme should be available to assist patient access.
Should a register of practitioners be developed, protections should be available for both
participating and objecting practitioners who do not wish to be identified for reasons of
harassment and stigma.
Provision could be made for practitioners who are willing to participate in restricted ways,
e.g. in a limited range of cases, or in only providing a second opinion.
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
28
3. Consent and potential coercion
Coercion of patients will be difficult to safeguard against completely. A significant proportion of the
terminally ill and elderly are estimated to experience some form of self-perceived burden. (125)
Coercion may also arise where individuals with poor access to good end-of-life care may choose
voluntary assisted dying even though symptom relief and a peaceful death could have been provided
if they had had appropriate access to end-of-life care.
Recommendations regarding consent and coercion:
Consideration must be given to enabling the exchange of information in formats accessible
to the patient such as in the patient’s preferred language, via sign language, interpreters, or
orally.
Legislative and regulatory measures must reflect the legitimate concerns that exist around
protection of vulnerable individuals or groups, especially where discussions may not be
perceived to have been fully transparent.
Data must be collected, monitored and reported in a manner that can pinpoint abuse at an
individual and population level.
Avenues to report and investigate suspected coercion must be built into any scheme
including via coronial review.
4. Conflict and bereavement support
Adequate family support, counselling and conflict mediation services will be required in the event of
legalisation. Frameworks for voluntary assisted dying are based on the culture-specific concept of
individual autonomy and do not generally acknowledge that end-of-life decisions are not made in a
vacuum.
The role, and the effect on family, carers and other loved ones are important considerations. What
support systems will be provided for individuals, families and health professionals who may be
involved, and who may suffer personal trauma or other harm as a result of this involvement,
regardless of whether or not the patient ultimately proceeds with a medically assisted death?
This must be dealt with in any proposed framework. The impact of conflict and bereavement can be
considerable, as can the stress on individual doctors receiving requests on a regular basis and at
varying levels of involvement. Doctors may, for example, face pressure from patients who are
deemed not to meet the criteria for access. Patients may also face pressure or coercion from family
members or carers.
Voluntary assisted dying may also lead to enduring conflict and complex grief for remaining family
members, carers and health professionals. Physicians may be placed in very difficult situations when
an individual wishes this but family members or other health professionals disagree with their
decision, and the family may blame the physician if it goes ahead. Evidence shows that many doctors
who have participated in voluntary assisted dying experience emotional distress.(29, 126) If a
proposal is legalised, there is a clear need for education, support and guidance for bereaved family
members and health professionals.
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
29
Recommendations regarding conflict and bereavement support:
Time for family/carer conferencing must be available to patients and health professionals to
acknowledge the impact on families and to enable family/carer participation and response.
Support systems must be provided for individuals, families and health professionals who
may be involved and who may suffer emotional distress, personal trauma or other harm as
a result of this involvement, regardless of whether or not the patient ultimately proceeds
with a medically assisted death.
Adequate funding will be required for such family support, counselling and conflict
mediation services.
5. Domains of expertise and training required of participating practitioners
Participating practitioners would also have to be properly skilled in a number of domains and would
have to be qualified in the diagnosis and prognosis of the specific medical condition(s) presenting in
each person requesting assistance in dying. Proposals could consider setting out the domains of
expertise required to provide voluntary assisted dying, rather than restricting it to a particular
profession or qualification level, which could create barriers to access or lead to an inexperienced
medical practitioner confirming a request.
For example, a neurologist who specialises in stroke care, and holds qualifications in neurology may
still not have sufficient experience of motor neurone disease management to be able to discuss
prognosis in detail or answer questions about artificial ventilation. This would need to be balanced
against the access issues that arise in regional and remote areas when patients are too sick to travel.
These situations would require detailed consideration around how assessment could be done by
someone suitably skilled.
Genuine engagement with the person must be a feature of any proposal to reduce the risk of doctor-
shoppingand multiple cursory assessments being undertaken by a small number of practitioners.
There is a need for assessment to be underpinned by a genuine and enduring relationship with the
person. This is an important safeguard to avoid reliance on potentially simplistic assessments/reviews
of paper documentation. Whilst the RACP has been made aware of recommendations for a
specifically trained occupational group/practitioners as an alternative approach, this concept has not
been further developed during preparation of this Statement.
Recommendations regarding expertise and training in the event of change to current law:
Upholding the trust society places in the medical profession is of key importance.
Participants must practise with the appropriate level of training, skill and experience, within
systems of collegial accountability.
Assessment of the requesting person must be underpinned by:
o a genuine and enduring relationship with the participating practitioner;
o a sufficient understanding of the patient’s preferences and values; and
o an informed understanding of the diagnosis and prognosis of the person’s medical
condition. (127)
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
30
Policymakers must safeguard against simplistic assessments/reviews of paper
documentation, doctor shopping”, inexperienced practitioners confirming requests and
cursory assessments being undertaken by a small number of practitioners.
Training, including clinical supervision where appropriate, must be adequately funded and
available for those practitioners interested and/or willing to participate, particularly in
relation to:
o the law and its implementation;
o communicating options at the end of life;
o the psychodynamic issues that may be involved in making and receiving requests;
o defining end-of-life and estimating life expectancy;
o exploring the reasons for a request;
o assessment of mental state and capacity in the context of end-of-life care;
o defining ‘suffering to the person that cannot be relieved in a manner that the
person considers tolerable’; and
o potential impact on already complex care.
This training must be available to all physicians, including Trainees who may be asked to
explore patient requests, even though legislation in Victoria does not permit them to
provide voluntary assisted dying.
The requirement for assessment to be done by someone suitably skilled would need to be
balanced against the equitable access issues that arise in regional and remote areas when
patients are too sick to travel.
To ensure legal clarity, clear and consistent guidance will need to be developed by relevant
authorities in consultation with the medical profession and other relevant health professions
on a range of practical issues, for example around attendance by a treating practitioner and
their obligations in the event the lethal dose is not effective.
Prudent prescribing and storage principles apply as much as ever; participating
practitioners must understand and communicate the possible outcomes and harms for
medications. In the case of intentionally lethal doses of medicines, this would include the
possibility that they are used otherwise than as intended, do not work and may cause
unwanted symptoms.
6. Reporting and evidence-based practice
A major practical role for involved physicians will be the capture of information around the quality,
performance and outcome of activities that result from legalisation. It is imperative that robust and
accurate records are kept both at the micro and macro levels and as part of the medical record.
Reporting must be undertaken directly to a monitoring body to track trends, patient motivations etc.
For example, there could be a specific reportable form filled out and sent to a monitoring body for
review.
Instances of voluntary assisted dying must be reported to enable audit of the scheme. It is
acknowledged there may be stigma felt by individuals in knowing that voluntary assisted dying may be
listed as the cause of death on the death certificate. Even so, there is overriding public interest in
having this information available in a de-identified manner. Enabling both the immediate and
underlying causes of death to be listed and reported should be considered. Cause of death data must
remain completely accurate for future planning of medical care. The cause of death must not only
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
31
include the terminal illness that made the patient eligible, but also that a substance was taken to
provide active assistance to the patient in dying.
All records in connection with a voluntary assisted death should be provided to a central body for
transparent monitoring and to enable important research on areas such as uptake, the reasons for
requests and requests amongst vulnerable groups. There should be a two-stage process, which
includes recording all requests, requests which are declined and patients who change their mind
following a request.
At a minimum, a central database of all who have requested and been approved to access voluntary
assisted dying and a research programme that reports the outcomes of the new legislation over time
will be necessary to track uptake and outcomes. Accurate and explainable records of all deaths that
occur due to voluntary assisted dying should be maintained. Patient-level reporting processes for
pharmacovigilance must also be built into any proposed scheme.
Monitoring should cover a range of areas including reasons for requests, conscientious objection,
disposal of unused lethal medication and impact on suicide rates more generally.
As a minimum a parliamentary committee should scrutinise the data collected and the operation of the
legislation. This might lead to amendment or further public consultation. If the introduction of voluntary
assisted dying is found to have negative or unintended effects, there must be a mechanism to review
or even withdraw legislation and to examine and manage problems arising in practice, unforeseen or
otherwise.
Recommendations regarding reporting and evidence-based practice:
A central database of all who have requested and been declined or approved to access
voluntary assisted dying and a research programme that transparently reports the uptake
and outcomes of the new legislation over time will be necessary. Areas of key interest
include the reasons for requests, patient demographics, requests amongst vulnerable
groups, impact on suicide rates, the disposal of unused lethal medication and patient -level
reporting processes for pharmacovigilance purposes.
Review of each individual case by a competent judicial officer (e.g. coroner) may be
required to ensure that the legislation has been complied with (parallel to the current
system of checks regarding deaths in medical care).
A parliamentary committee must scrutinise the data collected and the operation of the
legislation with the potential for its review, amendment, further public consultation or
withdrawal.
For future planning of medical care, cause of death data must remain completely accurate
by specifying the terminal illness that made the patient eligible and that a substance was
taken to provide voluntary assisted dying.
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
32
References
1. The Australian and New Zealand Society for Palliative Medicine. Position Statement
on the Practice of Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide. 2017.
2. Radbruch L, Carlo L, Bahr P, Müller-Busch C, Ellershaw J, de Conno F, et al.
Euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide: A white paper from the European Association for
Palliative Care. Palliative Medicine. 2016;30(2):104.
3. De Lima L, Woodruff R, Pettus K, Downing J, Buitrago R, Munyoro E, et al.
International Association for Hospice and Palliative Care Position Statement: Euthanasia
and Physician-Assisted Suicide. Journal of Palliative Medicine. 2017;20(1):8-14.
4. Australian and New Zealand Society for Geriatric Medicine. Euthanasia, Physician-
Assisted Suicide and End of Life Care Position Statement. 2014.
5. Australian Commission on Safety and Quality in Health Care (ACSQHC). National
Consensus Statement: essential elements for safe and high-quality end-of-life care. Sydney,
New South Wales, Australia: ACSQHC; 2015.
6. Palliative Care Subcommittee of the NZ Cancer Treatment Working Party. New
Zealand Palliative Care: A Working Definition. In: Ministry of Health, editor. Wellington, New
Zealand2007.
7. Ashby M. Of Life and Death: The Canadian and Australian Senates on Palliative
Care and Euthanasia. Journal of Law and Medicine. 1997;5:40-51.
8. Ashby M. Death causation in palliative medicine. In: Freckelton I. MD, editor.
Causation in law and medicine. Dartmouth: Ashgate; 2002.
9. Hunt R. Intention, the law, and clinical decision-making in terminal care. The Medical
Journal of Australia. 2001;175(10):516.
10. Thomson CJH. ‘… (D)eath, a necessary end, will come when it will come’, (William
Shakespeare, Julius Caesar, act 2, scene 2.). Intern Med J. 2011;41(6):439-40.
11. White BP, Willmott L, Ashby M. Palliative care, double effect and the law in Australia.
Intern Med J. 2011;41(6):485-92.
12. Sykes N, Thorns A. Sedative use in the last week of life and the implications for end-
of-life decision-making. Arch Intern Med. 2003;163(3):341-4.
13. Sykes N, Thorns A. The use of opioids and sedatives at the end of life. Lancet Oncol.
2003;4(5):312-8.
14. Good PD, Ravenscroft PJ, Cavenagh J. Effects of opioids and sedatives on survival
in an Australian inpatient palliative care population. Intern Med J. 2005;35(9):512-7.
15. Philp MR, Poolman M, Martin NP, Makin MK. Opioid use in the last days of life: what
is good practice? European Journal of Palliative Care. 2009;16(3):110-5.
16. George R, Regnard C. Lethal opioids or dangerous prescribers? Palliat Med.
2007;21(2):77-80.
17. Beller EM, van Driel ML, McGregor L, Truong S, Mitchell G. Palliative
pharmacological sedation for terminally ill adults. Cochrane Database Syst Rev.
2015;1:Cd010206.
18. Clark D. 'Total pain', disciplinary power and the body in the work of Cicely Saunders,
1958-1967. Soc Sci Med. 1999;49(6):727-36.
19. World Medical Association. WMA Declaration on Euthanasia 1987 [updated 2015.
Available from: https://www.wma.net/policies-post/wma-declaration-on-euthanasia/
20. Australian Medical Association. Position Statement on Euthanasia and Physician
Assisted Suicide 2016 2016 [Available from:
https://ama.com.au/system/tdf/documents/AMA%20Position%20Statement%20on%20Eutha
nasia%20and%20Physician%20Assisted%20Suicide%202016.pdf?file=1&type=node&id=45
402.
21. Rembert A. Teaching about Values: Remaining Neutral vs. Advocating One's Own
View. Peabody Journal of Education. 1976;53(2):71-5.
22. Roy DJ. Euthanasia and withholding treatment. In: al. De, editor. Oxford Textbook of
Palliative Care. 3rd Edition ed: Oxford University Press; 2005. p. 84-9.
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
33
23. Woodruff R. Euthanasia and Physician Assisted Suicide Are they clinically
necessary? : International Association for Hospice and Palliative Care; 1999 [Available from:
https://hospicecare.com/resources/ethical-issues/essays-and-articles-on-ethics-in-palliative-
care/euthanasia-and-physician-assisted-suicide-are-they-clinically-necessary.
24. Materstvedt LJ. The Euthanasia Debate Palliative care on the 'slippery slope’
towards euthanasia? Palliative Medicine. 2003;17(5):387-92.
25. Somerville M. Euthanasia: Is legalizing it a good idea? Australian Dialogues. 2011.
26. Schuklenk U, van Delden JJ, Downie J, McLean SA, Upshur R, Weinstock D. End-of-
life decision-making in Canada: the report by the Royal Society of Canada expert panel on
end-of-life decision-making. Bioethics. 2011;25 Suppl 1:1-73.
27. Foley K, Hendin, H. Eds. The case against Assisted Suicide for the right to End-of-
Life Care. Baltimore and London: John Hopkins University Press; 2002.
28. Quill TE, Battin, M.P. Eds. Physician Assisted Dying The case for palliative care
and patient choice. Baltimore and London: John Hopkins University Press; 2004.
29. Emanuel EJ, Onwuteaka-Philipsen BD, Urwin JW, Cohen J. Attitudes and Practices
of Euthanasia and Physician-Assisted Suicide in the United States, Canada, and Europe.
Jama. 2016;316(1):79-90.
30. Karlsson M, Milberg A, Strang P. Dying cancer patients' own opinions on euthanasia:
an expression of autonomy? A qualitative study. Palliat Med. 2012;26(1):34-42.
31. Terry W, Olson LG, Wilss L, Boulton-Lewis G. Experience of dying: concerns of dying
patients and of carers. Intern Med J. 2006;36(6):338-46.
32. Wilson KG, Chochinov HM, McPherson CJ, Skirko MG, Allard P, Chary S, et al.
Desire for euthanasia or physician-assisted suicide in palliative cancer care. Health Psychol.
2007;26(3):314-23.
33. Sullivan MD. The desire for death arises from an intolerable future rather than an
intolerable present. General Hospital Psychiatry.27(4):256-7.
34. Dees MK, Vernooij-Dassen MJ, Dekkers WJ, Vissers KC, van Weel C. 'Unbearable
suffering': a qualitative study on the perspectives of patients who request assistance in
dying. J Med Ethics. 2011;37(12):727-34.
35. Dees M, Vernooij-Dassen M, Dekkers W, van Weel C. Unbearable suffering of
patients with a request for euthanasia or physician-assisted suicide: an integrative review.
Psychooncology. 2010;19(4):339-52.
36. Kuhse H, Singer P, Baume P, Clark M, Rickard M. End-of-life decisions in Australian
medical practice. Med J Aust. 1997;166(4):191-6.
37. Deliens L, Mortier F, Bilsen J, Cosyns M, Vander Stichele R, Vanoverloop J, et al.
End-of-life decisions in medical practice in Flanders, Belgium: a nationwide survey. Lancet.
2000;356(9244):1806-11.
38. Meier DE, Emmons CA, Wallenstein S, Quill T, Morrison RS, Cassel CK. A national
survey of physician-assisted suicide and euthanasia in the United States. N Engl J Med.
1998;338(17):1193-201.
39. van der Maas PJ, van der Wal G, Haverkate I, de Graaff CL, Kester JG, Onwuteaka-
Philipsen BD, et al. Euthanasia, physician-assisted suicide, and other medical practices
involving the end of life in the Netherlands, 1990-1995. N Engl J Med. 1996;335(22):1699-
705.
40. Asch DA. The role of critical care nurses in euthanasia and assisted suicide. N Engl J
Med. 1996;334(21):1374-9.
41. Nuccetelli S, Seay G. Relieving pain and foreseeing death: a paradox about
accountability and blame. J Law Med Ethics. 2000;28(1):19-25, 2.
42. Cohen L, Ganzini L, Mitchell C, Arons S, Goy E, Cleary J. Accusations of murder and
euthanasia in end-of-life care. J Palliat Med. 2005;8(6):1096-104.
43. Douglas C. End-of-Life Decisions and Moral Psychology: Killing, Letting Die,
Intention and Foresight. Journal of Bioethical Inquiry. 2009;6(3):337-47.
44. Sulmasy DP. Commentary: Double effectIntention is the solution, not the problem.
The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics. 2000;28(1):26-9.
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
34
45. Cohen J, Marcoux I, Bilsen J, Deboosere P, van der Wal G, Deliens L. European
public acceptance of euthanasia: socio-demographic and cultural factors associated with the
acceptance of euthanasia in 33 European countries. Soc Sci Med. 2006;63(3):743-56.
46. Smith B. Cradled between heaven and earth. A reply to my patient's family: why I
couldn't offer active euthanasia when you asked for it. J Palliat Care. 2009;25(4):294-6.
47. Hall M, Trachtenberg F, Dugan E. The impact on patient trust of legalising physician
aid in dying. J Med Ethics. 2005;31(12):693-7.
48. van Delden JJ. Slippery slopes in flat countries--a response. J Med Ethics.
1999;25(1):22-4.
49. Pereira J. Legalizing euthanasia or assisted suicide: the illusion of safeguards and
controls. Curr Oncol. 2011;18(2):e38-45.
50. Pollard BJ. Can euthanasia be safely legalized? Palliat Med. 2001;15(1):61-5.
51. Kellehear A. The changing face of dying in Australia. Med J Aust. 2001;175(10):508-
10.
52. Magnusson RS. The Traditional Account of Ethics and Law at the End of Lifeand
its Discontents. Journal of Bioethical Inquiry. 2009;6(3):307-24.
53. Kirkey S. Take my name off the list, I can’t do any more’: Some doctors backing out
of assisted death. National Post. 2017 26 February 2017.
54. Rothschild A. Oregon: does physician-assisted suicide work? J Law Med.
2004;12(2):217-25.
55. Oregon Public Health Division. Death with Dignity Act Portland, Oregon, USA:
Oregon Health Authority; [Available from:
https://public.health.oregon.gov/ProviderPartnerResources/EvaluationResearch/DeathwithDi
gnityAct/Pages/index.aspx.
56. Steinbrook R. Physician-assisted death--from Oregon to Washington State. N Engl J
Med. 2008;359(24):2513-5.
57. Oregon Public Health Division Center for Health Statistics. Oregon Death With
Dignity Act Annual Report 2016. In: Authority OH, editor. Portland, Oregon, USA2016.
58. Public Health Division CfHS. Oregon Death with Dignity Act 2017 Data Summary.
2018. p. 14.
59. Loggers ET, Starks H, Shannon-Dudley M, Back AL, Appelbaum FR, Stewart FM.
Implementing a Death with Dignity program at a comprehensive cancer center. N Engl J
Med. 2013;368(15):1417-24.
60. Starks H, Pearlman RA, Hsu C, Back AL, Gordon JR, Bharucha AJ. Why now?
Timing and circumstances of hastened deaths. J Pain Symptom Manage. 2005;30(3):215-
26.
61. Pearlman RA, Hsu C, Starks H, Back AL, Gordon JR, Bharucha AJ, et al. Motivations
for physician-assisted suicide. J Gen Intern Med. 2005;20(3):234-9.
62. Hedberg K, Hopkins D, Leman R, Kohn M. The 10-year experience of Oregon's
Death with Dignity Act: 1998-2007. J Clin Ethics. 2009;20(2):124-32.
63. Stevens KR. Concentration of Oregon's Assisted Suicide Prescriptions & Deaths
from a Small Number of Prescribing Physicians: Physicians for Compassionate Care
Educational Foundation; 18 March 2015 [Available from:
http://www.pccef.org/resources/documents/ConcentrationofOregonsAssistedSuicideDeaths3
182015revision.pdf
64. Oregon Public Health Division Center for Health Statistics. Oregon Death With
Dignity Act Annual Reports 1998-2016. In: Authority OH, editor. Portland, Oregon, USA2016.
65. Washington State Department of Health. Death with Dignity Act Washington, USA
[Available from:
http://www.doh.wa.gov/YouandYourFamily/IllnessandDisease/DeathwithDignityAct
.
66. Ganzini L, Goy ER, Dobscha SK. Prevalence of depression and anxiety in patients
requesting physicians' aid in dying: cross sectional survey. BMJ. 2008;337:a1682.
67. Chambaere K, Vander Stichele R, Mortier F, Cohen J, Deliens L. Recent trends in
euthanasia and other end-of-life practices in Belgium. N Engl J Med. 2015;372(12):1179-81.
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
35
68. Onwuteaka-Philipsen BD, Brinkman-Stoppelenburg A, Penning C, de Jong-Krul GJ,
van Delden JJ, van der Heide A. Trends in end-of-life practices before and after the
enactment of the euthanasia law in the Netherlands from 1990 to 2010: a repeated cross-
sectional survey. Lancet. 2012;380(9845):908-15.
69. Committee RER. Regional Euthanasia Review Committee Annual Report 2016 2017
April 2017.
70. Dierickx S, Deliens L, Cohen J, Chambaere K. Euthanasia in Belgium: trends in
reported cases between 2003 and 2013. Cmaj. 2016;188(16):E407-e14.
71. Griffiths J, Weyers, H., Adams, M. Euthanasia and Law in Europe: Hart Publishing;
2008.
72. Keown J. The Law and Ethics of Medicine. Essays on the Inviolability of Human Life.
: Oxford University Press; 2013.
73. Quill T, Miller, F. (eds). Palliative Care and Ethics: Oxford University Press; 2014.
74. Younger S, Arnold, R. (eds.) Oxford Handbook of Ethics at the End of Life: Oxford
University Press; 2016.
75. Lerner BH, Caplan AL. Euthanasia in Belgium and the Netherlands: On a Slippery
Slope? JAMA Intern Med. 2015;175(10):1640-1.
76. Torjesen I. More people opt to use assisted dying laws for greater variety of reasons.
BMJ. 2015;351:h4332.
77. Ruijs CD, Kerkhof AJ, van der Wal G, Onwuteaka-Philipsen BD. Depression and
explicit requests for euthanasia in end-of-life cancer patients in primary care in the
Netherlands: a longitudinal, prospective study. Fam Pract. 2011;28(4):393-9.
78. Maessen M, Veldink JH, Onwuteaka-Philipsen BD, de Vries JM, Wokke JH, van der
Wal G, et al. Trends and determinants of end-of-life practices in ALS in the Netherlands.
Neurology. 2009;73(12):954-61.
79. Groenewoud JH, van der Heide A, Onwuteaka-Philipsen BD, Willems DL, van der
Maas PJ, van der Wal G. Clinical problems with the performance of euthanasia and
physician-assisted suicide in The Netherlands. N Engl J Med. 2000;342(8):551-6.
80. British Broadcasting Corporation. Belgium's parliament votes through child
euthanasia. 2014 13 February 2014.
81. Cohen J. End-of-Life decisions and place of death in Belgium and Europe. Brussels:
Vrije University; 2007.
82. Siegel AM, Sisti DA, Caplan AL. Pediatric euthanasia in Belgium: disturbing
developments. Jama. 2014;311(19):1963-4.
83. Kim SY, De Vries RG, Peteet JR. Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide of Patients With
Psychiatric Disorders in the Netherlands 2011 to 2014. JAMA Psychiatry. 2016;73(4):362-8.
84. Thienpont L, Verhofstadt M, Van Loon T, Distelmans W, Audenaert K, De Deyn PP.
Euthanasia requests, procedures and outcomes for 100 Belgian patients suffering from
psychiatric disorders: a retrospective, descriptive study. BMJ Open. 2015;5(7).
85. Chambaere K, Centeno C, Hernández EA, MSRTP YVW, Guillén-Grima F, Deliens
L, et al. Palliative care development in countries with a euthanasia law. Report for the
Commission on assisted dying briefing papers European Association of Palliative Care.
2011.
86. Battin MP, van der Heide A, Ganzini L, van der Wal G, Onwuteaka-Philipsen BD.
Legal physician-assisted dying in Oregon and the Netherlands: evidence concerning the
impact on patients in "vulnerable" groups. J Med Ethics. 2007;33(10):591-7.
87. Chambaere K. Euthanasia before and after its legalization in Belgium and the
Netherlands. Workshop: Euthanasia and palliative care Experiences and lessons to be
learned from Belgium and the Netherlands; End of Life Care Research Group, Department
of Medical Sociology, Faculty of Medicine and Pharmacy, Vrije University Brussels.
88. van der Heide A, Deliens L, Faisst K, Nilstun T, Norup M, Paci E, et al. End-of-life
decision-making in six European countries: descriptive study. Lancet. 2003;362(9381):345-
50.
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
36
89. Emanuel EJ, Fairclough DL, Daniels ER, Clarridge BR. Euthanasia and physician-
assisted suicide: attitudes and experiences of oncology patients, oncologists, and the public.
Lancet. 1996;347(9018):1805-10.
90. Cartwright CM, Williams GM, Parker MH, Steinberg MA. Does being against
euthanasia legislation equate to being anti-euthanasia? Intern Med J. 2006;36(4):256-9.
91. Steinberg MA, Najman JM, Cartwright CM, MacDonald SM, Williams GM. End-of-life
decision-making: community and medical practitioners' perspectives. Med J Aust.
1997;166(3):131-5.
92. Steinberg M, Cartwright C, Williams G, Robinson G, Tyler W. Survey of approval of
Australia's Northern Territory Rights of the Terminally Ill Act (1995). Lancet.
1997;349(9051):577.
93. Breitbart W, Rosenfeld BD, Passik SD. Interest in physician-assisted suicide among
ambulatory HIV-infected patients. Am J Psychiatry. 1996;153(2):238-42.
94. Lavery JV, Dickens BM, Boyle JM, Singer PA. Bioethics for clinicians: 11. Euthanasia
and assisted suicide. Cmaj. 1997;156(10):1405-8.
95. Wolfe J, Fairclough DL, Clarridge BR, Daniels ER, Emanuel EJ. Stability of Attitudes
Regarding Physician-Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia Among Oncology Patients,
Physicians, and the General Public. Journal of Clinical Oncology. 1999;17(4):1274-.
96. Valverius E, Nilstun T, Nilsson B. Palliative care, assisted suicide and euthanasia:
nationwide questionnaire to Swedish physicians. Palliat Med. 2000;14(2):141-8.
97. Magelssen M, Supphellen M, Nortvedt P, Materstvedt LJ. Attitudes towards assisted
dying are influenced by question wording and order: a survey experiment. BMC Med Ethics.
2016;17(1):24.
98. Blumer C. Vote Compass: Aussies want it, but euthanasia still a 'great untouched
issue' 2016 [Available from:
http://www.abc.net.au/news/2016-05-25/vote-compass-
euthanasia/7441176.
99. Essential Media Communications. Voluntary Euthanasia 6 December 2016 [Available
from: http://www.essentialvision.com.au/voluntary-euthanasia-6
.
100. The Australia Institute. Survey results - attitudes to voluntary euthanasia 6 January
2011 [Available from:
http://www.tai.org.au/sites/defualt/files/MR%20Survey%20results%20attitudes%20to%20vol
untary%20euthanasia_8.pdf.
101. Gower P. Poll: Kiwis want euthanasia legalised. Newshub. 2015 27 July 2015.
102. Research New Zealand. The majority of New Zealanders support the legalisation of
euthanasia 27 October 2016 [Available from:
http://www.researchnz.com/pdf/Media%20Releases/2016/Research%20New%20Zealand%2
0Media%20Release%20-%202016-10-28%20Euthanasia.pdf.
103. Karsoho H, Fishman JR, Wright DK, Macdonald ME. Suffering and medicalization at
the end of life: The case of physician-assisted dying. Soc Sci Med. 2016;170:188-96.
104. Zimmermann C, Rodin G. The denial of death thesis: sociological critique and
implications for palliative care. Palliat Med. 2004;18(2):121-8.
105. Higgins R, Moorfield, J.C. Tangihanga: Death customs. In: Ka’ai TM, Moorfield, J.C.,
Reilly, M.J.P., Moseley, S., editor. Ki te Whaiao: An introduction to Māori culture and society.
Auckland: Pearson Education; 2004.
106. Royal Australasian College of Physicians Māori Health Committee and New Zealand
CPD Committee. Guideline commentary on care and support of Māori and their whānau
around the time of death. 2011 [Available from:
https://www.racp.edu.au/docs/default-
source/default-document-library/guideline-commentary-on-care-maori-nz.pdf?sfvrsn=2.
107. White N, Reid F, Harris A, Harries P, Stone P. A Systematic Review of Predictions of
Survival in Palliative Care: How Accurate Are Clinicians and Who Are the Experts? PLoS
One. 2016;11(8):e0161407.
108. Snijdewind MC, van Tol DG, Onwuteaka-Philipsen BD, Willems DL. Developments in
the practice of physician-assisted dying: perceptions of physicians who had experience with
complex cases. J Med Ethics. 2016.
RACP Statement on Voluntary Assisted Dying: (2018)
37
109. Hudson PL, Kristjanson LJ, Ashby M, Kelly B, Schofield P, Hudson R, et al. Desire
for hastened death in patients with advanced disease and the evidence base of clinical
guidelines: a systematic review. Palliat Med. 2006;20(7):693-701.
110. Bruno MA, Bernheim JL, Ledoux D, Pellas F, Demertzi A, Laureys S. A survey on
self-assessed well-being in a cohort of chronic locked-in syndrome patients: happy majority,
miserable minority. BMJ Open. 2011;1(1):e000039.
111. Kirk TW, Mahon MM. National Hospice and Palliative Care Organization (NHPCO)
position statement and commentary on the use of palliative sedation in imminently dying
terminally ill patients. J Pain Symptom Manage. 2010;39(5):914-23.
112. Maltoni M, Pittureri C, Scarpi E, Piccinini L, Martini F, Turci P, et al. Palliative
sedation therapy does not hasten death: results from a prospective multicenter study. Ann
Oncol. 2009;20(7):1163-9.
113. Rietjens JA, van der Heide A, Vrakking AM, Onwuteaka-Philipsen BD, van der Maas
PJ, van der Wal G. Physician reports of terminal sedation without hydration or nutrition for
patients nearing death in the Netherlands. Ann Intern Med. 2004;141(3):178-85.
114. Broeckaert B. Palliative sedation, physician-assisted suicide, and euthanasia: "same,
same but different"? Am J Bioeth. 2011;11(6):62-4.
115. Steinhauser KE, Christakis NA, Clipp EC, McNeilly M, McIntyre L, Tulsky JA. Factors
considered important at the end of life by patients, family, physicians, and other care
providers. Jama. 2000;284(19):2476-82.
116. Douglas CD, Kerridge IH, Rainbird KJ, McPhee JR, Hancock L, Spigelman AD. The
intention to hasten death: a survey of attitudes and practices of surgeons in Australia. Med J
Aust. 2001;175(10):511-5.
117. New South Wales Government Attorney General's Department. Capacity Toolkit.
Sydney, NSW, Australia2008.
118. Stewart C, Peisah C, Draper B. A test for mental capacity to request assisted suicide.
J Med Ethics. 2011;37(1):34-9.
119. Chapman CR, Gavrin J. Suffering: the contributions of persistent pain. Lancet.
1999;353(9171):2233-7.
120. Swerissen H, Duckett, S., Farmer, J. Dying Well. Sydney, New South Wales,
Australia: Grattan Institute; 2014.
121. Statewide Health Service Strategy and Planning Unit; Health Commissioning
Queensland. Statewide strategy for end-of-life care. In: Department of Health, editor.
Brisbane, QLD, Australia: Queensland Government; 2015.
122. Muircroft WM, McKimm J, William L, MacLeod RD. A New Zealand perspective on
palliative care for Maori. J Palliat Care. 2010;26(1):54-8.
123. Lawrenson R, Smyth D, Kara E, Thomson R. Rural general practitioner perspectives
of the needs of Maori patients requiring palliative care. N Z Med J. 2010;123(1315):30-6.
124. Gott M, Allen R, Moeke-Maxwell T, Gardiner C, Robinson J. 'No matter what the
cost': A qualitative study of the financial costs faced by family and whanau caregivers within
a palliative care context. Palliat Med. 2015;29(6):518-28.
125. Gott M, Frey R, Wiles J, Rolleston A, Teh R, Moeke-Maxwell T, et al. End of life care
preferences among people of advanced age: LiLACS NZ BMC Palliative Care. 2017;16(76).
126. Stevens KR. Emotional and psychological effects of physician-assisted suicide and
euthanasia on participating physicians. Issues Law Med. 2006;21(3):187-200.
127. Australian Medical Association (Victoria). Physician Assisted Dying Position
Statement 2016 [Available from:
https://membership.amavic.com.au/files/DAM/Policy%20and%20Advocacy/2016/AMA%20Vi
ctoria%27s%20position%20statement%20on%20physician%20assisted%20dying.pdf.